Education’s Deep Roots: Historical Evidence for the Right to a Basic Minimum Education
For decades, the U.S. Supreme Court has left open the question whether the U.S. Constitution protects a right to some amount of education. While such a right is not specifically enumerated in the Constitution, advocates have long argued for the existence of an implicit, fundamental right to a basic minimum education under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Recognition of such a right requires grappling with the Supreme Court’s substantive due process jurisprudence. To be a fundamental right, one requirement is that a proposed right have deep roots in U.S. history and tradition. This Comment examines whether the right to a basic minimum education—defined as basic literacy—is deeply rooted.
While courts differ in how they analyze whether a right is deeply rooted, they all generally view the time around the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment as a relevant historical consideration. With a focus on that time period, this Comment analyzes two case studies: the Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands—or “Freedmen’s Bureau”—and the Bureau of Indian Affairs. In both cases, the federal government perceived a gap in local provision of education and responded through these agencies with support for literacy education. In serving as a backstop to local educational failures, the federal government’s actions ensured access to a basic literacy education. This pattern of behavior provides support for the notion that the right to a basic minimum education is deeply rooted.
“There have been periods when the country heard with dismay that ‘the soldier was abroad.’ That is not the case now. There is another person abroad, a less important person, in the eyes of some. The schoolmaster is abroad! And I trust more to him, armed with his primer, than I do to the soldier in full military array, for upholding and extending the liberties of the country.”
–Lord Brougham, The Schoolmaster Is Abroad, in The Freedmen’s Third Reader 201, 201 (Boston, The American Tract Society 1866).1
1This reader proved to be a popular reader series used in classrooms in Reconstruction Era southern schools. Jessica Enoch, Refiguring Rhetorical Education: Women Teaching African American, Native American, and Chicano/a Students, 1865–1911, at 35 (2008).
For twenty-six days in 2020, all students in Ohio, Kentucky, Tennessee, and Michigan could claim a fundamental right to a “basic minimum education” under the Fourteenth Amendment.2
Gary B. v. Whitmer (Gary B. I), 957 F.3d 616, 648 (6th Cir.), reh’g granted and vacated, 958 F.3d 1216 (6th Cir. 2020) (en banc).
The case, Gary B. v. Whitmer,3
957 F.3d 616 (6th Cir.), reh’g granted and vacated, 958 F.3d 1216 (6th Cir. 2020) (en banc).
Class Action Complaint at 5–14, Gary B. v. Snyder, 329 F. Supp. 3d 344 (E.D. Mich. 2018) (No. 2:16-cv-13292-SJM-APP).
Id. at 2.
Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 621.
Reversing the district court, the Sixth Circuit held that there was a fundamental, implicit right to what the court termed a “basic minimum education” under the Fourteenth Amendment.7
Id. at 648. Judge Eric Murphy dissented from the panel decision, arguing that the Fourteenth Amendment does not grant affirmative rights. Id. at 663 (Murphy, J., dissenting). But see id. at 656–57 (majority opinion) (explaining that the Supreme Court “has recognized affirmative fundamental rights” under the Fourteenth Amendment).
Id. at 652 (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720–21 (1997)).
While the Sixth Circuit held that the U.S. Constitution protects a right to a basic minimum education, the court declined to sketch out exactly what amount or kind of education this right guarantees.9
Id. at 659.
Id.
Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 659.
As the first federal appeals court decision establishing such a right, the Sixth Circuit’s holding was nothing short of groundbreaking.12
See History Is Made: Groundbreaking Settlement in Detroit Literacy Lawsuit, Pub. Couns. (May 14, 2020), https://perma.cc/Y23V-A9TH.
Gary B. v. Whitmer (Gary B. II), 958 F.3d 1216, 1216 (6th Cir. 2020) (en banc).
Id.
See Valerie Strauss, Michigan Settles Historic Lawsuit After Court Rules Students Have a Constitutional Right to a ‘Basic’ Education, Including Literacy, Wash. Post (May 14, 2020), https://perma.cc/7CLD-9WRM.
Colter Paulson, Sixth Circuit Vacates Right-to-Literacy Ruling, Nat’l L. Rev. (June 11, 2020), https://perma.cc/2NVB-CS7W.
While Gary B. is no longer binding law, the case remains of immense interest and importance to supporters of a right to education under the U.S. Constitution, as it is an indication that arguments for this right are not meritless.17
See, e.g., Mark Walsh, U.S. Appeals Court Recognizes a Federal Right of Access to Literacy, Educ. Wk. (Apr. 23, 2020), https://perma.cc/BXY7-Y7FM.
For more information about this history, see generally Steve Smith, Education Adequacy Litigation: History, Trends, and Research, 27 U. Ark. Little Rock L. Rev. 107 (2004).
Adult Literacy in the United States, Nat’l Ctr. for Educ. Stat. (July 2019), https://perma.cc/257J-XEY6.
Attorneys litigating a federal right to education have their work cut out for them, though, as they continue to face considerable obstacles. For starters, Supreme Court precedent presently limits the extent to which any kind of federal right to education can exist. Additionally, arguments for the existence of an implicit, fundamental right require diving headfirst into the Supreme Court’s substantive due process jurisprudence. A murky and “embattled area of constitutional law,” substantive due process analysis remains in “a state of profound doctrinal confusion.”20
Daniel O. Conkle, Three Theories of Substantive Due Process, 85 N.C. L. Rev. 63, 65 (2006).
One common thread in the “conceptual chaos” of substantive due process analysis is an eye toward history and tradition.21
Id. at 66.
Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 721 (1997) (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503 (1977) (plurality opinion)).
Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 652.
Critically though, how courts determine whether a right is deeply rooted is not a settled matter. A court’s determination depends on what analytical framework and choices the judge makes. One broad school of thought is that this analysis should be expansive, tracing a right through history to see where it originates, as well as if and how it changes over time.24
See, e.g., id. at 650 (“[T]his history should not be viewed as only a static point.”).
See, e.g., Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644, 715–16 (2015) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
See Jamal Greene, Fourteenth Amendment Originalism, 71 Md. L. Rev. 978, 979 (2012). While in the past decade the originalist view of this analysis has largely resided in the Court’s dissents, there is reason to believe that may change. With the recent confirmation of Justice Amy Coney Barrett, the Court’s originalist contingent is solidified for years to come. Moreover, the federal appellate and district court judges appointed by President Donald Trump have included a significant number of originalists. It would appear originalism is now in vogue. See How Amy Coney Barrett Would Reshape the Court—and the Country, Politico (Sept. 26, 2020), https://perma.cc/3A3F-8WUC.
These two analytical methods are often in conflict with one another. While the differences between these approaches are numerous, they have an obvious point of overlap: regardless of which methodology a judge subscribes to, the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment is relevant in determining whether a right is deeply rooted. For some, of course, it is the only time period worth considering. For others, though—particularly followers of the expansive approach—the Amendment’s enactment is still an important data point in U.S. history.
While existing scholarship provides solid, enactment-focused evidence supporting the deep roots of a right to education, it largely focuses on the attitudes and actions of state actors and state governments.27
See infra Part II.C.
For more on the Founders’ recognition of education’s importance, see Malhar Shah, Comment, The Fundamental Right to Literacy: Relitigating the Fundamental Right to Education After Rodriguez and Plyler, 73 Nat’l Law. Guild Rev. 129, 130–37 (2016).
Beginning in 1865—three years ahead of the Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification—and well into the 1870s, the federal government perceived gaps in local provision of education and positioned itself as a backstop to local and state failures in educating citizens. This positioning is apparent in two key case studies, both of which are largely unexplored by legal scholarship in the context of a right to education. The first is the Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands—or “Freedmen’s Bureau” for short. As a post–Civil War transition agency, the Freedmen’s Bureau responded to southern states’ deliberate failures to educate their Black citizens by supporting the creation of schools that encouraged literacy.29
See infra Part III.A.
See infra Part III.B.
To that end, this Comment will proceed in four parts. Part I explores past efforts at litigating a fundamental right to education under the U.S. Constitution and parses out the obstacles to establishing such a right. Part II lays out the role of the historical prong in the Supreme Court’s substantive due process test and highlights the value of enactment-focused evidence. Part III explores and examines each case study individually. Part IV brings these case studies into conversation with one another. Part IV also addresses the proverbial elephant in the room—the highly colonialist motivations behind these federal actions. This Comment concludes by arguing that, because of the actions the federal government took, there is support for the right to education’s deep roots, even with an enactment-era focus.
To understand present efforts to litigate a federal right to a basic minimum education, it is helpful to understand what the Supreme Court has already said about any potential right to education under the U.S. Constitution. However, before delving into the Court’s precedent, one distinction is useful. Many famous
examples of right-to-education cases come out of state courts; DeRolph v. State31
677 N.E.2d 733 (Ohio 1997). For more information on the aftermath of the DeRolph decision, see generally Larry J. Obhof, DeRolph v. State and Ohio’s Long Road to an Adequate Education, 2005 BYU Educ. & L.J. 83.
319 P.3d 1196 (Kan. 2014). For more information on the various stages of the decades-long educational adequacy litigation in Kansas, see generally Caroline DiBartolomeo, Comment, State Constitutional Law—Education Finance—The Ongoing Battle for Adequate School Funding in the State of Kansas. Gannon v. State, 390 P.3d 461 (Kan. 2017), 71 Rutgers U. L. Rev. 1257 (2019).
For a discussion of the developments of this movement in state courts, see Barry Friedman & Sara Solow, The Federal Right to an Adequate Education, 81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 92, 121–32 (2013).
An educational provision can be found in every single state constitution, but the guarantees of those provisions vary by state. Emily Parker, Educ. Comm’n of the States, 50-State Review: Constitutional Obligations for Public Education 1 (2016), https://perma.cc/XZA4-K5D3.
See Friedman & Solow, supra note 33, at 121–32.
One may wonder why it is useful to pursue a right to education under the Fourteenth Amendment if state constitutions already confer such a right. Two considerations are worth noting. First, in a nation with such uneven educational provision, additional protections—particularly protections that implicate the federal government as a distinct, additional system of enforcement—are valuable. Second, not all state educational provisions are created equal. Some state constitutions do not explicitly protect a certain quality of education or anything beyond the mere provision of public schools. See Parker, supra note 34, at 5–22.
Focusing then on a right to education under the U.S. Constitution, this Part will unpack what the Supreme Court has said—and has not said—about this proposed right. Part I.A explores the Court’s repeated emphasis on education’s importance leading up to 1973. Part I.B describes what changed in 1973—namely, how San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez37
411 U.S. 1 (1973).
The Supreme Court has long acknowledged the importance of education to American life. In 1923, less than a decade after the advent of compulsory schooling, the Supreme Court noted in Meyer v. Nebraska38
262 U.S. 390 (1923).
Id. at 400.
Id.
Act of Aug. 7, 1789, ch. 8, art. 3, 1 Stat. 50, 52.
Meyer, 262 U.S. at 400.
See Allen Pusey, Justices Hear a Challenge to ‘English-Only’ Laws, 103 A.B.A. J. 72, 72 (2017).
Meyer, 262 U.S. at 403.
This acknowledgement of education’s importance was not a one-off incident. In 1954, in the landmark case Brown v. Board of Education,45
347 U.S. 483 (1954).
Today, education is perhaps the most important function of state and local governments. Compulsory school attendance laws and the great expenditures for education both demonstrate our recognition of the importance of education to our democratic society. It is required in the performance of our most basic public responsibilities, even service in the armed forces. It is the very foundation of good citizenship.46
Id. at 493.
Here, the Court not only reiterated education’s importance; it connected that importance to the “very foundation” of citizenship and democratic society more broadly. The Court also acknowledged some additional functions of education, including “awakening the child to cultural values, [ ] preparing him for later professional training, and [ ] helping him to adjust normally to his environment.”47
Id.
Id. While the Court lauded education, it notably did not base Brown on the conclusion that school segregation laws violated students’ fundamental right to education.
Again, in 1972, the Court reaffirmed the importance of basic education to performing the functions of citizenry. In Wisconsin v. Yoder,49
406 U.S. 205 (1972).
Id. at 221.
Id. at 211–12.
Id. at 221.
While none of these cases speak squarely to a right to education under the Fourteenth Amendment, the Court in each case emphasized a longstanding national value on education in order to explain its decision. In Meyer and Brown, the importance of education underscored the Court’s decision to strike down restrictions on education. In Yoder, the agreement between the parties that education is important insofar as it teaches critical skills like reading served to cabin the reach of the Court’s decision. In all of these cases, the Court treated the historical and traditional importance of education as a near given. Yet despite the Court’s continued recognition of education’s importance, the question whether the Constitution protects a student’s right to education did not reach the Court until 1973.
While the Supreme Court heard oral arguments in Yoder, a monumental legal challenge was brewing in the south of Texas. After San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez, right-to-education advocates could no longer plausibly argue that the Fourteenth Amendment protected a broad, generalized right to education.
Demetrio Rodriguez, a sheet-metal welder residing in San Antonio, sent his children to the local Edgewood public schools.53
Michael Heise, The Story of San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez: School Finance, Local Control, and Constitutional Limits, in Education Law Stories 51, 52–53 (Michael A. Olivas & Ronna Greff Schneider eds., 2008).
Id. at 53.
Id.
Id.
Id.
Rodriguez and other families brought a challenge to the state’s funding system on behalf of Texas schoolchildren residing in districts with low property values. Rather than challenging the system under state law, the plaintiffs asserted that Texas’s funding system violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, which prohibits a state from “deny[ing] to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.”58
U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1.
See Selene C. Vázquez, Note, The Equal Protection Clause & Suspect Classifications: Children of Undocumented Entrants, 51 U. Mia. Inter-Am. L. Rev. 63, 64–65 (2020).
Here, the plaintiffs argued that Texas’s school funding system classified based on wealth and that wealth was a suspect classification meriting strict scrutiny review. Additionally, the plaintiffs argued that strict scrutiny was warranted because the classification implicated a fundamental interest—namely, education.60
Heise, supra note 53, at 54, 56; see also Rodriguez v. San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist., 337 F. Supp. 280, 282 (W.D. Tex. 1971), rev’d, 411 U.S. 1 (1973).
Rodriguez, 337 F. Supp. at 285.
Id. at 285–86.
Texas appealed the panel’s judgment directly to the U.S. Supreme Court.63
Heise, supra note 53, at 59.
Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 17.
Id. at 28.
Id. at 35.
With these words, the Supreme Court closed the door on a general “right to education” under the Fourteenth Amendment. But upon closing that door, the Court opened a window. Even though the Court held that there is no broad-reaching, general right to education under the U.S. Constitution, the Rodriguez Court did hypothesize that some minimum amount of education could be fundamental and thus protected. The Court wrote, “Even if it were conceded that some identifiable quantum of education is a constitutionally protected prerequisite to the meaningful exercise of [other constitutional rights,] we have no indication that the present levels of educational expenditures in Texas provide an education that falls short.”67
Id. at 36–37.
Since Rodriguez, the Supreme Court has occasionally revisited what that “identifiable quantum of education” looks like, but the issue has largely been treated incidentally and indirectly. Take, for instance, Papasan v. Allain.68
478 U.S. 265 (1986).
Id. at 267–68.
To understand the plaintiffs’ claim, one must understand the history and purpose of these land grants. In 1785, Congress—in positioning the nation for westward expansion—established requirements for surveying and selling the Northwest Territory.70
C. Maison Heidelberg, Note, Closing the Book on the School Trust Lands, 45 Vand. L. Rev. 1581, 1584 (1992).
Id.
Id. at 1586.
Papasan, 478 U.S. at 271.
Id.
Id.
Id. at 272.
Heidelberg, supra note 70, at 1586 n.21.
Papasan, 478 U.S. at 272.
Id. at 273.
Id. at 274.
The Supreme Court rejected this contention. Writing for the Court, Justice Byron White dismissed the plaintiffs’ allegations in the complaint as mere legal conclusions lacking sufficient factual support. He noted that the complaint did not allege that students in these counties were “not taught to read or write; they d[id] not allege that they receive[d] no instruction on even the educational basics.”81
Id. at 286.
Id.
While Papasan did not resolve the question whether there is a fundamental right to some amount of education, the Court’s opinion is important in two ways. First, it gave an indication of what facts could support a claim that one’s right to some amount of education had been violated. Clearly, grave educational malpractice must occur. Second, the case confirmed that whether the Fourteenth Amendment guarantees a right to some minimal amount of education is still an open question after Rodriguez.83
See Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 642 (“While the Supreme Court has repeatedly discussed this issue, it has never decided it, and the question of whether such a right exists remains open today.”); see also Derek W. Black, The Fundamental Right to Education, 94 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1059, 1061–62 (2019).
In bringing those cases, advocates for a right to education not only run up against the limits of Supreme Court precedent; they also encounter obstacles in the Court’s jurisprudence surrounding substantive due process analysis. This Part lays out those obstacles and focus on one in particular—the Court’s historical inquiry. Part II.A provides a brief overview of substantive due process analysis generally, including the requirement that courts consider U.S. history and tradition. Part II.B explores the varying approaches to this historical inquiry and identifies a point of commonality between these approaches. Finally, Part II.C lays out how an enactment-focused study of federal involvement in literacy education would aid followers of both approaches.
Substantive due process derives from the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.84
Conkle, supra note 20, at 65–66.
U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1.
Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 643.
Id.
See Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720 (1997) (collecting cases).
Determining what constitutes a fundamental right is challenging. As an initial matter, courts proceed with extreme reluctance when litigants request recognition of a new fundamental right.89
See, e.g., Collins v. City of Harker Heights, 503 U.S. 115, 125 (1992) (“As a general matter, the Court has always been reluctant to expand the concept of substantive due process because guideposts for responsible decisionmaking in this unchartered area are scarce and open-ended.” (citing Regents of the Univ. of Mich. v. Ewing, 474 U.S. 214, 225–26 (1985))).
See Glucksberg, 521 U.S. at 720.
Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2584, 2598 (2015) (“The identification and protection of fundamental rights is an enduring part of the judicial duty to interpret the Constitution. That responsibility, however, ‘has not been reduced to any formula.’” (quoting Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 542 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting))).
Washington v. Glucksberg92
521 U.S. 702 (1997).
Id. at 720, 726.
Id. at 720–21 (quotation marks and citations omitted) (first quoting Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503 (1977) (plurality opinion); and then quoting Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325, 326 (1937)).
Id. at 721 (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Reno v. Flores, 507 U.S. 292, 302 (1993)).
This Comment focuses solely on the first prong of that first feature—an analysis of whether the proposed right is “objectively, deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.” This inquiry has been dubbed “the historical prong of the Supreme Court’s substantive due process test.”96
Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 652 (“[W]e find that the right to a basic minimum education . . . meet[s] the historical prong of the Supreme Court’s substantive due process test.”).
Interestingly, while scholarship addresses both additional requirements, whether the right to education is implicit in the concept of ordered liberty receives far more scholarly attention than whether this right is carefully described. See, e.g., Shah, supra note 28, at 137 (arguing that a right to literacy is implicit in the concept of ordered liberty).
When confronted with a standard like the “deeply rooted” consideration, a natural follow-up question is: How does a court know if a right is deeply rooted? Like many legal standards, the answer is not totally clear.
To understand how courts analyze an asserted right’s historical roots, it can be helpful to think about why history merits consideration in substantive due process analysis at all. The primary rationale for doing so is largely rooted in judicial restraint.98
See, e.g., Glucksberg, 521 U.S. at 721 (“Our Nation’s history, legal traditions, and practices thus provide the crucial guideposts for responsible decision-making that direct and restrain our exposition of the Due Process Clause.” (quotation marks and citation omitted) (quoting Collins, 503 U.S. at 125)).
Michael W. McConnell, The Right to Die and the Jurisprudence of Tradition, 1997 Utah L. Rev. 665, 672.
Judges can also fall victim to “law office history”—a derogatory term employed by historians when lawyers or judges cherry-pick certain quotations or happenings to support a given legal argument. Law office history can prove “manipulable.” Thomas Hilbink, Schooling: History as Handmaiden, 5 Law, Culture & Humans. 43, 44–47 (2009).
See John C. Toro, The Charade of Tradition-Based Substantive Due Process, 4 N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty 172, 181–94 (2009).
Judges do agree that the “deeply rooted” question is a historical inquiry. Yet in endeavoring to answer whether a proposed right is deeply rooted, a principal source of disagreement among judges is how to conduct that historical analysis. There is unfortunately no guidebook. Different judges espouse different methodol-ogies, and this results in a number of unclear points.
One major uncertainty in this realm is what kind of evidence to consult. At various points, the Supreme Court has considered many different types of evidence. Supreme Court precedent on this historical analysis includes the use of quotes from past cases, brief tours through ancient Roman law, and considerations of briefs from historians.102
See id. at 181–86.
The temporal limits on what evidence one can use are also not uniform. Should evidence of a right’s deep roots be limited to the time surrounding the enactment of the Fourteenth Amendment? Should there be any limits at all? These questions are unsettled, and judges frequently disagree.103
See Ronald Turner, On Substantive Due Process and Discretionary Traditionalism, 66 SMU L. Rev. 841, 847 (2013).
576 U.S. 644 (2015).
1. Differing methodologies in Obergefell.
Obergefell exemplifies how, in recent years, the Court has taken an expansive approach to its historical analysis by tracing proposed rights through history.105
See Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 643–44.
Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2598. Some scholars argue that Obergefell effectively overrules Glucksberg, but this interpretation is controversial. See Ronald Turner, W(h)ither Glucksberg?, 15 Duke J. Const. L. & Pub. Pol’y 183, 209–16 (2020) (describing and rejecting such contentions). Of course, even assuming arguendo that Obergefell’s approach supplants that of Glucksberg, tradition and history remain relevant, even if they do not totally control the fundamental rights inquiry.
Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2593–94.
Id. at 2594–96.
society.109
Id. at 2594.
Id. at 2607–08.
In dissent, Justice Antonin Scalia railed against the majority’s use of such expansive evidence in its historical analysis. In doing so, he espoused a completely different evidentiary limit. Justice Scalia wrote that the Court had “no basis for striking down a practice that is not expressly prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment’s text, and that bears the endorsement of a long tradition of open, widespread, and unchallenged use dating back to the Amendment’s ratification.”111
Id. at 2628 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2628 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
Id.
Of course, this time stamp of “ratification” is itself not so definite as it may appear. While the Fourteenth Amendment was officially enacted in 1868, ratification is a process rather than a single moment in time. Proposals for the Fourteenth Amendment can be traced to a proposal before the Joint Committee on Reconstruction in 1865, and the amendment in its final form did not receive the requisite approval from both houses of Congress until June 13, 1866.114
On This Day, Congress Approved the 14th Amendment, Nat’l Const. Ctr. (June 13, 2020), https://perma.cc/V34A-U2KE.
Landmark Legislation: The Fourteenth Amendment, U.S. Senate, https://perma.cc/FRL3-7HQP.
2. The methodological overlap.
Reading the majority opinion and Justice Scalia’s dissent together, Obergefell exemplifies two opposing theories of the historical inquiry. Justice Kennedy presents a far-reaching, holistic analysis of history that consequently draws on historical sources from a wide array of time periods. In contrast, Justice Scalia offers an enactment-focused analysis with strict temporal limits. Proponents of each method can point to a number of shortcomings in the opposing approach. Followers of the expansive method critique the enactment-focused analysis as unnecessarily restrictive.116
See, e.g., Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 650 (“[T]his history should not be viewed as only a static point.”).
See Katharine T. Bartlett, Tradition as Past and Present in Substantive Due Process Analysis, 62 Duke L.J. 535, 555 (2012).
Cf. Richard S. Myers, Obergefell and the Future of Substantive Due Process, 14 Ave Maria L. Rev. 54, 68 (2016) (noting that substantive due process outcomes are not inevitable as “[m]uch depends on the Court’s personnel at the time the issue comes before the Justices”).
While these two theories are clearly different, they overlap in their view of the enactment’s relevance in conducting this analysis. In Justice Scalia’s dissent, this is easy to see. Indeed—to paraphrase William Shakespeare—for him, the enactment’s the thing.119
William Shakespeare, Hamlet act 2, sc. 2, l. 593 (Oxford 1987) (“The play’s the thing.”).
1. Previous scholarship.
While the time around the amendment’s enactment is relevant no matter the methodology, there is nonetheless little scholarship laying out the enactment-focused case for a deeply rooted right to education. That is why this Comment will place its focus there. True, scholars like Professors Steven Calabresi and Sarah Agudo have argued that the right is deeply rooted based on an examination of state constitutions around the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment.120
Steven G. Calabresi & Sarah E. Agudo, Individual Rights Under State Constitutions When the Fourteenth Amendment Was Ratified in 1868: What Rights Are Deeply Rooted in American History and Tradition?, 87 Tex. L. Rev. 7, 108 (2008).
Id.
Id.
Black, supra note 83, at 1063.
Id. at 1063–64.
Id. at 1063.
Id. at 1067.
Id. at 1090.
Black, supra note 83, at 1090 (citation omitted).
While scholars like Calabresi, Agudo, and Black all provide valuable insights into education’s deep roots at the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment, their evidence largely focuses on the states. Enacting an amendment requires state and federal actors. Yet, while state constitutions and state constitutional conventions illuminate the attitudes of key state actors, they do not tell us much about the federal government’s actions. This Comment seeks to remedy that by analyzing two key federal, enactment-era programs: the Freedmen’s Bureau’s support for southern schools after the Civil War and the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ creation of compulsory boarding schools for indigenous children.
2. Terminology.
Before undertaking an enactment-focused analysis of this right’s historical roots, a clarification of scope and terms is helpful. Because a general right to education is foreclosed by Rodriguez, this Comment focuses on whether—as the Supreme Court hypothesized—“some identifiable quantum of education” is deeply rooted.129
Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 36. Notably, in conducting this historical analysis, Rodriguez is of limited value. Rodriguez predates Glucksberg, and thus, while the Court acknowledged the importance of education, it did not explore the proposed right’s historical roots.
For a comparison of educational provisions in state constitutions, see generally Parker, supra note 34.
Beyond the term itself, what this “basic minimum education” could entail is not settled, as discussed in Part I. However, for the sake of argumentative clarity, this Comment assumes that that right at the very least encompasses, as the Sixth Circuit suggested, “a foundational level of literacy.”131
Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 659.
Why the focus on literacy? First, this approach is in line with the obvious notion that literacy skills are required in nearly every aspect of modern life, from filling out a job application to paying taxes and voting. Indeed, “[t]he importance of literacy in modern society cannot be over-emphasized.”132
Literacy’s importance to everyday activities is not the only reason it is so critical. A lack of functional literacy can not only hinder a person’s ability to perform these critical activities, but it can also negatively affect other cognitive skills like memory, attention, and calculation. Roger T. Wilson, Literacy and Its Significance in Modern Life, 13 Colleagues 9, 10 (2016).
Adult Literacy in the United States, supra note 19.
More critically though, this approach is in line with the Court’s conceptualization of what amount of education could feasibly be protected by the U.S. Constitution. In Rodriguez, the Court rejected plaintiffs’ claims and noted that they had not claimed—nor could they—that Texas’s funding system “fail[ed] to provide each child with an opportunity to acquire the basic minimal skills necessary for the enjoyment of the rights of speech and of full participation in the political process.”134
Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 37.
Papasan, 478 U.S. at 286.
This Comment explores two key federal actions around the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment: the educational support provided by the Freedmen’s Bureau and the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ creation of compulsory boarding schools for indigenous children. This Part explores how these federal programs began, how they operated, and to what extent literacy education played a role.
Before undertaking those case studies, one may wonder why the case study method is a valuable means of performing this analysis at all. The reasoning lies partly in pragmatism and partly in historical methodology. To the former, case studies offer a reasonable scope to an otherwise unwieldy analysis. Even for judges who only consider the time around the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment, there is a lot of potential evidence to consider—state constitutions, state ratification conventions, and
legislative history are just a few. Expand that to fit the needs of a judge who takes a holistic approach, and the scope quickly becomes overwhelming. Case studies offer clear parameters and save the discussion from spiraling into a multivolume encyclopedia. Beyond the practical considerations, the case study method also finds support in historical practice. Historians routinely adopt narrow foci to answer big questions.136
A well-known example is an article by Professor Wendy Anne Warren, which focuses on one paragraph in a seventeenth-century colonial travelogue to demonstrate the flaws in historical accounts of that period. See generally Wendy Anne Warren, “The Cause of Her Grief”: The Rape of a Slave in Early New England, 93 J. Am. Hist. 1031 (2007).
See supra note 100.
In a similar vein, one may wonder why these federal actions are valuable case studies to analyze. In a historical analysis, the selection of evidence is crucial. These two examples are valuable because, unlike state constitutions138
See Calabresi & Agudo, supra note 120, at 108.
See Black, supra note 83, at 1090.
Cf. Conkle, supra note 20, at 134 n.398 (noting that congressional action is relevant to determining evolving national values).
A. The Freedmen’s Bureau
TOPJust two months before General Robert E. Lee’s famous surrender at Appomattox Court House, the Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands—“Freedmen’s Bureau”—was born through an act of Congress.141
Freedmen’s Bureau, History (Oct. 3, 2018), https://perma.cc/LC6G-WRTA.
Ch. 90, 13 Stat. 507.
Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1865 § 1, 13 Stat. at 507–08.
Freedmen’s Bureau, supra note 141.
Id.
See id.; Amy Dru Stanley, From Bondage to Contract: Wage Labor, Marriage, and the Market in the Age of Slave Emancipation 42 (1998).
See Eric Foner, A Short History of Reconstruction, 1863–1877, at 65 (1990) (“Bureau schools nonetheless helped lay the foundation for Southern public education. Education probably represented the agency’s greatest success in the postwar South.”).
1. The Education Division’s organization.
The value the Bureau placed on education is evidenced by the organization of its Education Division. In this context, the meaning of “organization” is twofold. The Bureau was organized in the sense that its Education Division had a sophisticated, hierarchical structure that enabled wide outreach in the South. It was also organized in the sense that it created and maintained detailed records on this structure and its operations.
The structure of the Bureau’s Education Division tracked closely with the structure of the Bureau at large. Each district had a superintendent of education who reported to the superintendent in the Bureau’s Washington, D.C., office. Reports were due from each district’s superintendent of education on the first of every month, even during the summer when most schools were out of session.148
During the summer months, the reports generally included a remark about how many schools were closed for the season. See, e.g., Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Report of Schools in Alabama for Month of August, 1866 (1866), microformed on Records of the Education Division of the Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, 1865–1871, Roll 15 (Nat’l Archives) [hereinafter Records of the Education Division].
The meticulousness of the Bureau’s educational recordkeeping is notable. These records not only tracked the number of schools in a district, but they also collected detailed information about the pupils in attendance. The Bureau went so far as to compile and maintain records of students enrolled in literacy classes specifically.149
See, e.g., Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Abstract of Reports of State Superintendents for Month of October, 1866 (1866), microformed on Records of the Education Division, Roll 33.
See id.
See id.
Black, supra note 83, at 1065–66.
In some districts, the data collection form changed to include an additional area for the state superintendent of education to note the number of “places now destitute where schools might be organized” as well as the number of “pupils (estimated) who would attend such schools.”153
Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Report of the Superintendent of Education, Bureau R., F. & A.L., State of Alabama, for the Month of July 1869 (1869), microformed on Records of the Education Division, Roll 15.
Indeed, the Bureau’s structure enabled this flexible, differentiated response to the needs of different districts. As a result, how the Bureau approached school establishment and support varied by district. The Bureau did purchase and maintain ownership over a number of school buildings throughout the South.154
They kept detailed records on this aspect of their work as well. See, e.g., Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Report of School Buildings Owned by Bureau R., F. & A.L. and by Other Parties Engaged in the Education of Freedmen, in the State of Alabama Month of June 1870 (1870), microformed on Records of the Education Division, Roll 15.
See African Americans and Education During Reconstruction: The Tolson’s Chapel Schools, Nat’l Park Serv., https://perma.cc/6BQ2-QLZY(last updated Oct. 6, 2020).
See id.
The Bureau’s structure and recordkeeping enabled it to track and expand literacy education to areas where state governments were unable or unwilling to do so. This is itself evidence of the federal government’s role in ensuring access to literacy education. As Part II.A.2 details, though, the Bureau’s increasing educational outreach during this time was made possible by Congress, who codified and supported that educational mission. This support allowed the Bureau to last for as long as it did and elevate its educational mission.
2. The longevity and positioning of the Bureau’s educational mission.
The Bureau’s tenure and role was in jeopardy at multiple points throughout the Reconstruction Era, but the educational mission nevertheless remained a consistently critical part of the Bureau’s operation. In 1866, with the Bureau’s initial yearlong tenure set to expire, Congress passed the Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866.157
Ch. 200, 14 Stat. 173.
A notable opponent of both the Freedmen’s Bureau and the codification of its educational role was President Andrew Johnson. On February 19, 1866, to the surprise of many in Congress,158
Mark A. Graber, The Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill’s Constitution, 94 Tex. L. Rev. 1361, 1367 (2016).
Andrew Johnson, Veto Message to the Senate (Feb. 19, 1866), in Veto Messages of the Presidents of the United States, with the Action of Congress Thereon 289, 292 (Washington, Government Printing Office 1886).
That the commissioner of this bureau shall at all times co-operate with private benevolent associations of citizens in aid of freedmen, and with agents and teachers, duly accredited and appointed by them, and shall hire or provide by lease buildings for purposes of education whenever such associations shall, without cost to the government, provide suitable teachers and means of instruction, and he shall furnish such protection as may be required for the safe conduct of such schools.160
160Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866 § 13, 14 Stat. at 176.
President Johnson once again vetoed the bill, but this time, Congress had enough votes to override his veto.161
Freedmen’s Bureau Acts of 1865 and 1866, U.S. Senate, https://perma.cc/C8Q9-YDBT.
Of course, one may wonder whether President Johnson’s response undermines the notion that the right to a basic minimum education is deeply rooted. While the President—an admittedly key piece of the federal government—may have attempted to quash this bill and the Bureau’s educational mission, Congress’s response is crucial here. That is because it is Congress, not the President, that has a role in constitutional amendments.162
See U.S. Const. art. V.
In 1868, the tenure of the Freedmen’s Bureau was once again up for debate. This time, Congress clarified an exit strategy for the Bureau. The Act of July 16, 1868, provided “[t]hat it shall be the duty of the Secretary of War to discontinue the operations of the bureau in any State whenever such State shall be fully restored in its constitutional relations with the government of the United States, and shall be duly represented in the Congress.”163
Act of July 6, 1868, ch. 135, § 2, 15 Stat. 83, 83.
Act of July 6, 1868 § 2, 15 Stat. at 83.
Compare Act of July 6, 1868 § 2, 15 Stat. at 83, with Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866 § 5, 14 Stat. at 174, and Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1865 §§ 2, 4, 13, 13 Stat. at 508.
This requirement that southern states retain the Bureau until education was sufficiently provided for fits nicely within Black’s account of that same Congress. He emphasized Congress’s requirement that states introduce education provisions into their constitutions in order to be readmitted to the Union.166
Black, supra note 83, at 1063.
See Landmark Legislation: The Fourteenth Amendment, supra note 115.
This first case study already provides key evidence that the right to a basic minimum education is deeply rooted. As a post-war transition agency, the Bureau was a federal entity designed to support primarily Black citizens. The Bureau viewed their mission as preparing these “new” citizens to participate fully in democratic society. A key part of executing that mission was supporting the establishment of schools, as educating Black people while they were enslaved was illegal in much of the antebellum South. Those schools in turn prioritized literacy, and in reporting on the progress of those schools, the Bureau prioritized literacy as well. This educational role of the Bureau was crucial. Its importance was reflected in the duration of the Bureau’s educational capacity, even persisting through a presidential veto. Moreover, as the federal government looked to readmit rebel states into the United States, the Bureau’s educational function remained statutorily authorized until the state could properly educate its entire citizenry. This requirement dovetailed other readmission criteria, including the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment and the inclusion of an educational provision in each state’s constitution. In this way, the federal government ensured access to a basic minimum education. As a result, this case study supports that the right to a basic minimum education has deep, enactment-focused roots.
B. The Bureau of Indian Affairs’ Compulsory Boarding Schools
TOPTurning to the second case study, a similar pattern of federal intervention emerges. Part III.B focuses on the federal actions behind the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ compulsory boarding schools for indigenous youths. In sharp contrast to the Freedmen’s Bureau’s relatively short lifespan, the Bureau of Indian Affairs was created in 1824, decades before the Civil War and Reconstruction.168
Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA), U.S. Dep’t of the Interior, https://perma.cc/8HB3-FN8U.
Id.
David Wallace Adams, Education for Extinction: American Indians and the Boarding School Experience, 1875–1928, at 26–27 (1995).
Raymond Cross, American Indian Education: The Terror of History and the Nation’s Debt to the Indian Peoples, 21 U. Ark. Little Rock L. Rev. 941, 952 (1999).
To properly investigate this case study, this Section proceeds as follows. Part III.B.1 describes early federal education commitments to indigenous people, explores the changing legal status of indigenous people during the nineteenth century, and explains how those changes impact the analysis of literacy education’s
historical roots. Part III.B.2 then dives into the structure of these schools and the degree to which literacy received emphasis.
1. Education and the changing legal status of indigenous people.
Like the Bureau of Indian Affairs itself, educational commitments to indigenous people did not begin in the 1860s or 1870s. Federal commitments to the education of indigenous children can be traced far before the Reconstruction Era. Indeed, “the United States pledged to provide a suitable education for the American Indian peoples” in the Northwest Ordinance of 1787.172
Id. at 950.
By 1871, just three years after the enactment of the Fourteenth Amendment, the United States had ratified more than 110 treaties that promised some amount of education to indigenous children.173
See David. H. DeJong, Promises of the Past: A History of Indian Education in the United States 34 (1993).
Cross, supra note 171, at 950–52.
Id. at 954.
To understand why this shift occurred, it is critical to understand that the legal status of indigenous people changed dramatically over the course of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. At the nation’s Founding, their legal status was something close to that of independent nations whose lands largely lay beyond the borders of the original thirteen states.176
Robert B. Porter, The Demise of the Ongwehoweh and the Rise of the Native Americans: Redressing the Genocidal Act of Forcing American Citizenship upon Indigenous Peoples, 15 Harv. BlackLetter L.J. 107, 110–11 (1999).
Id. at 129–30.
For a discussion of this evolving “wardship” status, see generally Nancy Carol Carter, Race and Power Politics as Aspects of Federal Guardianship over American Indians: Land-Related Cases, 1887–1924, 4 Am. Indian L. Rev. 197 (1976).
See, e.g., Porter, supra note 176, at 115–16.
The changing legal status of indigenous people during this time makes analyzing the federal government’s creation of compulsory boarding schools especially intriguing. With the conception of indigenous children and the tribes they were a part of as “wards,” there are two conflicting roads of analysis one could take. First, one could say that the wardship status shifts the role of the federal government such that it drove the federal government to do more than it would otherwise. In other words, because wardship is such a dependent state, federal officials’ actions do not reflect what they believed to be necessary for a functioning society but instead was something they thought would just be beneficial to this special class of people. Essentially, this argument requires assuming that these educational programs are products of benevolence or pity rather than perceived necessity. Besides the host of problems that accompany assuming such motivations on behalf of the architects of these schools, this attitude, to put it lightly, does not track with the rest of the federal government’s interactions with indigenous peoples in the nineteenth century.180
For a sample of this treatment, see generally David E. Wilkins, American Indian Politics and the American Political System (2007).
If the federal government was not going above and beyond, that leaves an alternative. The federal government undertook a federalized education program because federal officials believed that program to be necessary for these children to function in “civilized” society. This notion tracks both with the government’s general policy toward indigenous peoples and with the expressed motivations of the program’s architects. For example, Merrill Gates, a critical member of the indigenous children’s education movement, reflected: “Is not a guardian’s first duty so to educate and care for his wards as to make them able to care for themselves?”181
Merrill E. Gates, Land and Law as Agents in Educating Indians, in H.R. Doc. No. 109, Seventeenth Annual Report of the Board of Indian Commissioners, The Year 1885 (1886), reprinted in Americanizing the American Indians: Writings by the “Friends of the Indian,” 1880–1900, at 46 (Francis Paul Prucha ed., 1973).
Id. at 46, 52.
See Porter, supra note 176, at 115–23.
One could argue that the unique legal status of indigenous people during this period renders this case study particularly ill-suited to a conversation about what the Fourteenth Amendment protects because the Amendment was not interpreted to change the legal status of Native Americans into citizens.184
See id. at 133–34, 136.
Pub. L. No. 68-175, 43 Stat. 253.
Id. at 124.
Thomas J. Morgan, Instructions to Indian Agents in Regard to Inculcation of Patriotism in Indian Schools, in H.R. Exec. Doc. No. 51-1, pt. 5, at clxvii (1890), reprinted in Americanizing the American Indians, supra note 181, at 257.
The changing legal status of indigenous people during the nineteenth century is important context to this case study. It explains why federal attitudes toward indigenous children’s education shifted from the Founding to the 1870s. This context is important, and if anything, it makes this case study even more worthy of attention. The federal government saw its mission as preparing its wards for U.S. citizenship. As Part III.B.2 now explores, that preparation always involved basic literacy education.
2. Literacy’s role in compulsory boarding schools.
Literacy featured prominently in the federal government’s compulsory schools because of the perceived link between literacy and civilized society. As the U.S. commissioner of education would describe the educational mission of these schools years after their founding, the schools would “give [indigenous children] letters, and make them acquainted with the printed page. . . . With these comes the great emancipation, and the school shall give [ ] that.”188
W.T. Harris, The Relation of School Education to the Work of Civilizing Other Races (1895), reprinted in Proceedings of the Thirteenth Annual Meeting of the Lake Mohonk Conference of Friends of the Indian 33, 37 (Isabel C. Barrows ed., Boston, The Lake Mohonk Conference 1896).
See Jon Reyhner, American Indian Boarding Schools: What Went Wrong? What Is Going Right?, 57 J. Am. Indian Educ. 58, 60 (2018).
See Sarah Klotz, Impossible Rhetorics of Survivance at the Carlisle School, 1879–1883, 69 Coll. Composition & Commc’n, 208, 212 (2017) (placing “the boarding school project within a long history of literacy training as settler colonialism in North America” (emphasis in original)); see also Adams, supra note 170, at 137.
See Adams, supra note 170, at 137–38.
Outside of class, the importance of literacy was reinforced through the production of school newspapers, which featured student compositions and highlighted student achievements.192
See Klotz, supra note 190, at 212–13.
Id. at 213.
Embe, Stiya, a Carlisle Indian Girl at Home (Cambridge, Riverside Press 1891).
Amanda J. Zink, Carlisle’s Writing Circle: Boarding School Texts and the Decolonization of Domesticity, 27 Stud. in Am. Indian Literatures 37, 37 (2015).
Id. at 37–38.
Embe, supra note 194, at 108.
Id.
Id.
In this way, Stiya embodied both the importance of literary education to school officials and the reason why reading received so much emphasis. To them, reading enabled students to both fully engage in society and assimilate their family and homes into that society.
Because school officials deemed reading to be so critical in this process, they attached severe consequences to seemingly minor reading stumbles. For example, when students failed to read a passage aloud correctly, students could expect harsh critiques and even discipline from their instructors.200
See Adams, supra note 170, at 138–41.
See Klotz, supra note 190, at 212–13.
See Adams, supra note 170, at 25–27, 140–41, 291.
Before that discussion begins, it is worthwhile to take stock of the federal government’s behavior in this context. The federal government saw education as a key step in making indigenous people U.S. citizens. When the federal government perceived a failure in educational provision of local schools on reservations, they responded with a federal program of schools. Much like the Southern schools supported by the Freedmen’s Bureau, these schools prioritized literacy. Through literacy, the architects of these schools hoped to prepare students and their families for U.S. citizenship. This pattern of thinking and action maps closely onto the cycle of behavior the federal government displayed through the Freedmen’s Bureau’s educational projects.
With an understanding of how each case study speaks to the deep roots of a right to a basic minimum education, it is now time to bring those case studies into conversation with each other. While the actions undertaken by the Freedmen’s Bureau and the Bureau of Indian Affairs bear many similarities to one another, one similarity requires discussion first and foremost: both of these programs are inextricable from the colonialist motivations that underpin them. Part IV.A wrestles with this similarity. After unpacking these programs’ motivations, Part IV.A goes on to explain how these motivations impact a proposed right to a basic minimum education. Finally, Part IV.B concludes by showing that these programs—though problematically motivated—ultimately support the notion that the right to a basic minimum education has deep roots.
The colonialism behind the actions of the Bureau of Indian Affairs and the Freedmen’s Bureau is unmistakable. Consider first the compulsory boarding schools for indigenous children. The principal motivations behind these schools are hardly difficult to discern. With a stated goal of “[k]ill[ing] the Indian in him, and sav[ing] the man,”203
Richard H. Pratt, The Advantages of Mingling Indians with Whites (1892), reprinted in Americanizing the American Indians, supra note 181, at 260–61; see also Adams, supra note 170, at 52.
Adams, supra note 170, at 141 (quotation marks omitted).
See generally Lori V. Quigley, Thomas Indian School Social Experiment Resulting in Traumatic Effects, 14 Jud. Notice 48 (2019).
With a much more complicated legacy, the Freedmen’s Bureau has received both praise and critique for its operations. Praise derives from the Bureau’s position of often working against the racism and revanchism in the postwar South. Popular websites laud the Bureau as a triumph through characterizations like the following: “During its years of operation, the Freedmen’s Bureau fed millions of people, built hospitals and provided medical aid, negotiated labor contracts for ex-slaves and settled labor disputes. It also helped former slaves legalize marriages and locate lost relatives, and assisted black veterans.”206
Freedmen’s Bureau, supra note 141.
See Stanley, supra note 146, at 36.
Id. at 36–37.
No part of examining these actions should be equated with absolving these federal officials from their condemnable motivations and actions. A narrative suggesting that these actions were purely the products of altruism or even attempts at reparation would be deeply flawed. The point of examining these actions is not to praise the federal government. The point of examining these actions is to show that the federal government deemed education to be essential, so much so that it expended time on the Congress floor, dedicated resources from the national budget, and premised independent statehood on literacy education. It did so because it perceived that the states and private organizations had failed. These actions placed the federal government in such a position that it essentially served as a backstop, ensuring that where local educational provision failed, literacy education could still occur.
Of course, the colonialism underpinning these programs may lead one to think that these programs were not truly educational initiatives and rather that they were assimilationist and racist programs. The complicated, messy reality is that they were a bit of both. True, the reason that Congress and federal agents undertook these missions was based on problematic assumptions. In both case studies, they assumed in one form or another that people of color innately lacked the ability to engage in democratic society. These assumptions are obviously wrong. Yet, the programs federal officials created—while undeniably operating with these biases—were programs that prioritized educational provision, specifically where local actors had failed to do so. The reasoning behind these programs is unquestionably important and should under no circumstances be erased from accounts of these actions. But it is the actions the federal government took that define whether they protected a right to a basic minimum education. In the case of both the Freedmen’s Bureau and the Bureau of Indian Affairs, they did in fact protect and support educational access to literacy.
Bad motivations can and do beget law that ultimately receives modern approval under a different rationale. Take, for example, worker protection laws like those establishing a minimum wage. The history of minimum wage laws can be traced to beliefs in the inherent inferiority of women.209
See Raymund Munts & David C. Rice, Women Workers: Protection or Equality?, 24 Indus. & Labor Rels. Rev. 3, 3–5 (1970).
State Minimum Wages, Nat’l Conf. of State Legislatures (Jan. 5, 2021), https://perma.cc/54VK-YYYN.
With this notion in mind, the remainder of this Part discusses the role that the federal government ultimately assumed at the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment and how that bears on the question of whether foundational literacy education is deeply rooted in U.S. history and tradition.
With the understanding of a right to a basic minimum education as at least a right to some foundational level of literacy, this right has deep roots within the federal government around the time of the enactment. Indeed, the federal government at the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment effectively positioned itself as an ensurer of access to literacy instruction in areas where that access was believed to be extremely lacking or nonexistent.
First, consider the Freedmen’s Bureau. The Congress that ratified the Fourteenth Amendment is the same Congress that passed the Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866, codifying the Bureau’s educational mission over the concerns of the president. In fact, after President Johnson’s first veto, Congress put the bill on hold in order to ratify the Fourteenth Amendment. This is the same Congress that—despite President Johnson’s disapproval of the Bureau’s educational goals—codified that educational role regardless. When it came time to disband the Bureau, exiting a given state was made dependent on the status of its educational system. Both in supporting the establishment of schools and in making their operation a prerequisite of unencumbered statehood, the federal government expanded opportunities to access literacy education.
One may argue that these programs are not truly evidence of a right to a basic minimum education, but rather they are a policy response to the extraordinary circumstances of the Civil War and Reconstruction. This argument might have more credence if the federal government ceased its educational involvement after Reconstruction ended. But it didn’t. Federal boarding schools still exist today,211
Reyhner, supra note 189, at 74.
See generally Ctr. on Educ. Pol’y, A Brief History of the Federal Role in Education: Why It Began & Why It’s Still Needed (1990).
One may also argue that the federal government’s focus on the South undercuts any argument that it assumed a role in ensuring educational access. However, this ignores the fact that the concentration of efforts in the South responded to an obvious need. Prior to the Civil War, many southern states made it a crime to teach enslaved people to read.213
Black, supra note 83, at 1065–66.
Moreover, the Freedmen’s Bureau was not the only example of the federal government engaging in this type of behavior. In devising compulsory schools for indigenous children, the federal government engaged in a similar cycle of behavior. It assessed the current state of education and determined it was lacking. In response, it used federal funds to create schools to address the perceived gap.214
See Adams, supra note 170, at 26–27.
These case studies and the cycle of federal behavior that they both share mean that the federal government has a history of ensuring access to a minimum amount of education—specifically, basic literacy education—when it determines that local entities have failed. This history is directly from the period of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment and thus supports the notion that the right to a basic minimum education has deep roots in our nation’s history.
Bringing this support in conversation with other scholarship, the historical roots of a right to a basic minimum education abound. As this Comment addresses, the very notion of the federal government as a backstop to local educational failure has deep roots at the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment. This conclusion buttresses other findings about education’s history, from the right’s inclusion in nearly every state constitution to the relationship between those education provisions and readmission to the Union. Moreover, this mountain of evidence is just a small drop in the bucket if one embraces an expansive view of the histo-rical prong, bringing in evidence like the advent of compulsory schooling and the early twentieth-century Supreme Court precedent discussed in Part I.A—as the Sixth Circuit did in Gary B.215
See Gary B. I, 957 F.3d 650–52.
With considerable support for the right’s deep roots under both of the prong’s analytical frameworks, advocates for such a right have multiple avenues of making their case. While advocates still must convince judges that the right is implicit in the concept of ordered liberty and carefully described, a recognized right may be closer than it appears.
Scholarship about a right to education has long been sidelined as fantastical theory rather than adopted by courts. After all, the Supreme Court explicitly foreclosed a broad, general right to education under the Fourteenth Amendment. Yet scholars and courts have acknowledged that the Court left open the question whether a right to some minimum amount of education exists. And indeed, the Sixth Circuit’s opinion in Gary B.—albeit short-lived—has demonstrated that arguments for this right’s recognition are not meritless. If a federal court of appeals can reach this conclusion, it is no longer fantasy to think that other courts might follow suit.
The path to a recognized right certainly contains obstacles. One key issue that advocates will have to wrestle with is the historical prong of substantive due process analysis. While judges today differ in how they analyze whether a proposed right is deeply rooted in U.S. history and tradition—from an expansive analytical approach to an enactment-focused one—the importance of identifying and analyzing those roots around the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s enactment is the same. Previous scholarship highlights important evidence from state constitutions and constitutional conventions, arguing that the pervasive discussions and guarantees of education in these sources indicate that the right is deeply rooted. Critically however, these state-focused pieces of evidence are not the only support available for this notion. Indeed, the federal government’s actions in supporting the Freedmen’s Bureau’s educational operations and the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ compulsory boarding schools for indigenous children both stand as distinct, interrelated examples of the government prioritizing, providing, and protecting literacy education as a necessity.
In both cases, the federal government assessed the state of education in a region, decided it was deeply lacking, and took it upon itself to establish or support the establishment of schools to address that issue. True, the government did not establish a federal system of public schools for all children. Instead, the government responded to areas it identified as high need by acting to ensure that at least some access to education existed. This education always included a literacy component. This positioning of education as a protected necessity is evidence that even when limiting one’s evidence to around the time of the Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification and enactment, the right to a basic minimum education is deeply rooted in U.S. history and tradition.
Importantly, even if courts hold that the right to a basic minimum education is deeply rooted, additional requirements must be shown before that right could be recognized. Per the Supreme Court’s articulation of substantive due process analysis in Glucksberg, the asserted right to education must still be carefully described.216
See Glucksberg, 521 U.S. at 721.
Id. (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325, 326 (1937)).
There is considerable scholarship arguing that both requirements are indeed met. See generally Black, supra note 83; Friedman & Solow, supra note 33.
See Black, supra note 83, 1089–90.
In the midst of all this theoretical uncertainty regarding whether the Fourteenth Amendment protects a right to a basic minimum education, one fact is certain. The U.S. education system is failing to provide fundamental skills like reading, especially to the most marginalized Americans.220
See Adult Literacy in the United States, supra note 19.
Aaron Tang, Ethan Hutt & Daniel Klasik, Opinion, A Constitutional Right to Literacy for Detroit’s Kids?, N.Y. Times (Apr. 26, 2020), https://perma.cc/E24E-5STP(arguing that systemic inequality in U.S. education cannot be properly addressed solely in federal courts).
- 1This reader proved to be a popular reader series used in classrooms in Reconstruction Era southern schools. Jessica Enoch, Refiguring Rhetorical Education: Women Teaching African American, Native American, and Chicano/a Students, 1865–1911, at 35 (2008).
- 2Gary B. v. Whitmer (Gary B. I), 957 F.3d 616, 648 (6th Cir.), reh’g granted and vacated, 958 F.3d 1216 (6th Cir. 2020) (en banc).
- 3957 F.3d 616 (6th Cir.), reh’g granted and vacated, 958 F.3d 1216 (6th Cir. 2020) (en banc).
- 4Class Action Complaint at 5–14, Gary B. v. Snyder, 329 F. Supp. 3d 344 (E.D. Mich. 2018) (No. 2:16-cv-13292-SJM-APP).
- 5Id. at 2.
- 6Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 621.
- 7Id. at 648. Judge Eric Murphy dissented from the panel decision, arguing that the Fourteenth Amendment does not grant affirmative rights. Id. at 663 (Murphy, J., dissenting). But see id. at 656–57 (majority opinion) (explaining that the Supreme Court “has recognized affirmative fundamental rights” under the Fourteenth Amendment).
- 8Id. at 652 (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720–21 (1997)).
- 9Id. at 659.
- 10Id.
- 11Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 659.
- 12See History Is Made: Groundbreaking Settlement in Detroit Literacy Lawsuit, Pub. Couns. (May 14, 2020), https://perma.cc/Y23V-A9TH.
- 13Gary B. v. Whitmer (Gary B. II), 958 F.3d 1216, 1216 (6th Cir. 2020) (en banc).
- 14Id.
- 15See Valerie Strauss, Michigan Settles Historic Lawsuit After Court Rules Students Have a Constitutional Right to a ‘Basic’ Education, Including Literacy, Wash. Post (May 14, 2020), https://perma.cc/7CLD-9WRM.
- 16Colter Paulson, Sixth Circuit Vacates Right-to-Literacy Ruling, Nat’l L. Rev. (June 11, 2020), https://perma.cc/2NVB-CS7W.
- 17See, e.g., Mark Walsh, U.S. Appeals Court Recognizes a Federal Right of Access to Literacy, Educ. Wk. (Apr. 23, 2020), https://perma.cc/BXY7-Y7FM.
- 18For more information about this history, see generally Steve Smith, Education Adequacy Litigation: History, Trends, and Research, 27 U. Ark. Little Rock L. Rev. 107 (2004).
- 19Adult Literacy in the United States, Nat’l Ctr. for Educ. Stat. (July 2019), https://perma.cc/257J-XEY6.
- 20Daniel O. Conkle, Three Theories of Substantive Due Process, 85 N.C. L. Rev. 63, 65 (2006).
- 21Id. at 66.
- 22Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 721 (1997) (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503 (1977) (plurality opinion)).
- 23Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 652.
- 24See, e.g., id. at 650 (“[T]his history should not be viewed as only a static point.”).
- 25See, e.g., Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644, 715–16 (2015) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
- 26See Jamal Greene, Fourteenth Amendment Originalism, 71 Md. L. Rev. 978, 979 (2012). While in the past decade the originalist view of this analysis has largely resided in the Court’s dissents, there is reason to believe that may change. With the recent confirmation of Justice Amy Coney Barrett, the Court’s originalist contingent is solidified for years to come. Moreover, the federal appellate and district court judges appointed by President Donald Trump have included a significant number of originalists. It would appear originalism is now in vogue. See How Amy Coney Barrett Would Reshape the Court—and the Country, Politico (Sept. 26, 2020), https://perma.cc/3A3F-8WUC.
- 27See infra Part II.C.
- 28For more on the Founders’ recognition of education’s importance, see Malhar Shah, Comment, The Fundamental Right to Literacy: Relitigating the Fundamental Right to Education After Rodriguez and Plyler, 73 Nat’l Law. Guild Rev. 129, 130–37 (2016).
- 29See infra Part III.A.
- 30See infra Part III.B.
- 31677 N.E.2d 733 (Ohio 1997). For more information on the aftermath of the DeRolph decision, see generally Larry J. Obhof, DeRolph v. State and Ohio’s Long Road to an Adequate Education, 2005 BYU Educ. & L.J. 83.
- 32319 P.3d 1196 (Kan. 2014). For more information on the various stages of the decades-long educational adequacy litigation in Kansas, see generally Caroline DiBartolomeo, Comment, State Constitutional Law—Education Finance—The Ongoing Battle for Adequate School Funding in the State of Kansas. Gannon v. State, 390 P.3d 461 (Kan. 2017), 71 Rutgers U. L. Rev. 1257 (2019).
- 33For a discussion of the developments of this movement in state courts, see Barry Friedman & Sara Solow, The Federal Right to an Adequate Education, 81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 92, 121–32 (2013).
- 34An educational provision can be found in every single state constitution, but the guarantees of those provisions vary by state. Emily Parker, Educ. Comm’n of the States, 50-State Review: Constitutional Obligations for Public Education 1 (2016), https://perma.cc/XZA4-K5D3.
- 35See Friedman & Solow, supra note 33, at 121–32.
- 36One may wonder why it is useful to pursue a right to education under the Fourteenth Amendment if state constitutions already confer such a right. Two considerations are worth noting. First, in a nation with such uneven educational provision, additional protections—particularly protections that implicate the federal government as a distinct, additional system of enforcement—are valuable. Second, not all state educational provisions are created equal. Some state constitutions do not explicitly protect a certain quality of education or anything beyond the mere provision of public schools. See Parker, supra note 34, at 5–22.
- 37411 U.S. 1 (1973).
- 38262 U.S. 390 (1923).
- 39Id. at 400.
- 40Id.
- 41Act of Aug. 7, 1789, ch. 8, art. 3, 1 Stat. 50, 52.
- 42Meyer, 262 U.S. at 400.
- 43See Allen Pusey, Justices Hear a Challenge to ‘English-Only’ Laws, 103 A.B.A. J. 72, 72 (2017).
- 44Meyer, 262 U.S. at 403.
- 45347 U.S. 483 (1954).
- 46Id. at 493.
- 47Id.
- 48Id. While the Court lauded education, it notably did not base Brown on the conclusion that school segregation laws violated students’ fundamental right to education.
- 49406 U.S. 205 (1972).
- 50Id. at 221.
- 51Id. at 211–12.
- 52Id. at 221.
- 53Michael Heise, The Story of San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez: School Finance, Local Control, and Constitutional Limits, in Education Law Stories 51, 52–53 (Michael A. Olivas & Ronna Greff Schneider eds., 2008).
- 54Id. at 53.
- 55Id.
- 56Id.
- 57Id.
- 58U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1.
- 59See Selene C. Vázquez, Note, The Equal Protection Clause & Suspect Classifications: Children of Undocumented Entrants, 51 U. Mia. Inter-Am. L. Rev. 63, 64–65 (2020).
- 60Heise, supra note 53, at 54, 56; see also Rodriguez v. San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist., 337 F. Supp. 280, 282 (W.D. Tex. 1971), rev’d, 411 U.S. 1 (1973).
- 61Rodriguez, 337 F. Supp. at 285.
- 62Id. at 285–86.
- 63Heise, supra note 53, at 59.
- 64Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 17.
- 65Id. at 28.
- 66Id. at 35.
- 67Id. at 36–37.
- 68478 U.S. 265 (1986).
- 69Id. at 267–68.
- 70C. Maison Heidelberg, Note, Closing the Book on the School Trust Lands, 45 Vand. L. Rev. 1581, 1584 (1992).
- 71Id.
- 72Id. at 1586.
- 73Papasan, 478 U.S. at 271.
- 74Id.
- 75Id.
- 76Id. at 272.
- 77Heidelberg, supra note 70, at 1586 n.21.
- 78Papasan, 478 U.S. at 272.
- 79Id. at 273.
- 80Id. at 274.
- 81Id. at 286.
- 82Id.
- 83See Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 642 (“While the Supreme Court has repeatedly discussed this issue, it has never decided it, and the question of whether such a right exists remains open today.”); see also Derek W. Black, The Fundamental Right to Education, 94 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1059, 1061–62 (2019).
- 84Conkle, supra note 20, at 65–66.
- 85U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1.
- 86Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 643.
- 87Id.
- 88See Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720 (1997) (collecting cases).
- 89See, e.g., Collins v. City of Harker Heights, 503 U.S. 115, 125 (1992) (“As a general matter, the Court has always been reluctant to expand the concept of substantive due process because guideposts for responsible decisionmaking in this unchartered area are scarce and open-ended.” (citing Regents of the Univ. of Mich. v. Ewing, 474 U.S. 214, 225–26 (1985))).
- 90See Glucksberg, 521 U.S. at 720.
- 91Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2584, 2598 (2015) (“The identification and protection of fundamental rights is an enduring part of the judicial duty to interpret the Constitution. That responsibility, however, ‘has not been reduced to any formula.’” (quoting Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 542 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting))).
- 92521 U.S. 702 (1997).
- 93Id. at 720, 726.
- 94Id. at 720–21 (quotation marks and citations omitted) (first quoting Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503 (1977) (plurality opinion); and then quoting Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325, 326 (1937)).
- 95Id. at 721 (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Reno v. Flores, 507 U.S. 292, 302 (1993)).
- 96Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 652 (“[W]e find that the right to a basic minimum education . . . meet[s] the historical prong of the Supreme Court’s substantive due process test.”).
- 97Interestingly, while scholarship addresses both additional requirements, whether the right to education is implicit in the concept of ordered liberty receives far more scholarly attention than whether this right is carefully described. See, e.g., Shah, supra note 28, at 137 (arguing that a right to literacy is implicit in the concept of ordered liberty).
- 98See, e.g., Glucksberg, 521 U.S. at 721 (“Our Nation’s history, legal traditions, and practices thus provide the crucial guideposts for responsible decision-making that direct and restrain our exposition of the Due Process Clause.” (quotation marks and citation omitted) (quoting Collins, 503 U.S. at 125)).
- 99Michael W. McConnell, The Right to Die and the Jurisprudence of Tradition, 1997 Utah L. Rev. 665, 672.
- 100Judges can also fall victim to “law office history”—a derogatory term employed by historians when lawyers or judges cherry-pick certain quotations or happenings to support a given legal argument. Law office history can prove “manipulable.” Thomas Hilbink, Schooling: History as Handmaiden, 5 Law, Culture & Humans. 43, 44–47 (2009).
- 101See John C. Toro, The Charade of Tradition-Based Substantive Due Process, 4 N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty 172, 181–94 (2009).
- 102See id. at 181–86.
- 103See Ronald Turner, On Substantive Due Process and Discretionary Traditionalism, 66 SMU L. Rev. 841, 847 (2013).
- 104576 U.S. 644 (2015).
- 105See Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 643–44.
- 106Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2598. Some scholars argue that Obergefell effectively overrules Glucksberg, but this interpretation is controversial. See Ronald Turner, W(h)ither Glucksberg?, 15 Duke J. Const. L. & Pub. Pol’y 183, 209–16 (2020) (describing and rejecting such contentions). Of course, even assuming arguendo that Obergefell’s approach supplants that of Glucksberg, tradition and history remain relevant, even if they do not totally control the fundamental rights inquiry.
- 107Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2593–94.
- 108Id. at 2594–96.
- 109Id. at 2594.
- 110Id. at 2607–08.
- 111Id. at 2628 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
- 112Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2628 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
- 113Id.
- 114On This Day, Congress Approved the 14th Amendment, Nat’l Const. Ctr. (June 13, 2020), https://perma.cc/V34A-U2KE.
- 115Landmark Legislation: The Fourteenth Amendment, U.S. Senate, https://perma.cc/FRL3-7HQP.
- 116See, e.g., Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 650 (“[T]his history should not be viewed as only a static point.”).
- 117See Katharine T. Bartlett, Tradition as Past and Present in Substantive Due Process Analysis, 62 Duke L.J. 535, 555 (2012).
- 118Cf. Richard S. Myers, Obergefell and the Future of Substantive Due Process, 14 Ave Maria L. Rev. 54, 68 (2016) (noting that substantive due process outcomes are not inevitable as “[m]uch depends on the Court’s personnel at the time the issue comes before the Justices”).
- 119William Shakespeare, Hamlet act 2, sc. 2, l. 593 (Oxford 1987) (“The play’s the thing.”).
- 120Steven G. Calabresi & Sarah E. Agudo, Individual Rights Under State Constitutions When the Fourteenth Amendment Was Ratified in 1868: What Rights Are Deeply Rooted in American History and Tradition?, 87 Tex. L. Rev. 7, 108 (2008).
- 121Id.
- 122Id.
- 123Black, supra note 83, at 1063.
- 124Id. at 1063–64.
- 125Id. at 1063.
- 126Id. at 1067.
- 127Id. at 1090.
- 128Black, supra note 83, at 1090 (citation omitted).
- 129Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 36. Notably, in conducting this historical analysis, Rodriguez is of limited value. Rodriguez predates Glucksberg, and thus, while the Court acknowledged the importance of education, it did not explore the proposed right’s historical roots.
- 130For a comparison of educational provisions in state constitutions, see generally Parker, supra note 34.
- 131Gary B. I, 957 F.3d at 659.
- 132Literacy’s importance to everyday activities is not the only reason it is so critical. A lack of functional literacy can not only hinder a person’s ability to perform these critical activities, but it can also negatively affect other cognitive skills like memory, attention, and calculation. Roger T. Wilson, Literacy and Its Significance in Modern Life, 13 Colleagues 9, 10 (2016).
- 133Adult Literacy in the United States, supra note 19.
- 134Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 37.
- 135Papasan, 478 U.S. at 286.
- 136A well-known example is an article by Professor Wendy Anne Warren, which focuses on one paragraph in a seventeenth-century colonial travelogue to demonstrate the flaws in historical accounts of that period. See generally Wendy Anne Warren, “The Cause of Her Grief”: The Rape of a Slave in Early New England, 93 J. Am. Hist. 1031 (2007).
- 137See supra note 100.
- 138See Calabresi & Agudo, supra note 120, at 108.
- 139See Black, supra note 83, at 1090.
- 140Cf. Conkle, supra note 20, at 134 n.398 (noting that congressional action is relevant to determining evolving national values).
- 141Freedmen’s Bureau, History (Oct. 3, 2018), https://perma.cc/LC6G-WRTA.
- 142Ch. 90, 13 Stat. 507.
- 143Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1865 § 1, 13 Stat. at 507–08.
- 144Freedmen’s Bureau, supra note 141.
- 145Id.
- 146See id.; Amy Dru Stanley, From Bondage to Contract: Wage Labor, Marriage, and the Market in the Age of Slave Emancipation 42 (1998).
- 147See Eric Foner, A Short History of Reconstruction, 1863–1877, at 65 (1990) (“Bureau schools nonetheless helped lay the foundation for Southern public education. Education probably represented the agency’s greatest success in the postwar South.”).
- 148During the summer months, the reports generally included a remark about how many schools were closed for the season. See, e.g., Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Report of Schools in Alabama for Month of August, 1866 (1866), microformed on Records of the Education Division of the Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, 1865–1871, Roll 15 (Nat’l Archives) [hereinafter Records of the Education Division].
- 149See, e.g., Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Abstract of Reports of State Superintendents for Month of October, 1866 (1866), microformed on Records of the Education Division, Roll 33.
- 150See id.
- 151See id.
- 152Black, supra note 83, at 1065–66.
- 153Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Report of the Superintendent of Education, Bureau R., F. & A.L., State of Alabama, for the Month of July 1869 (1869), microformed on Records of the Education Division, Roll 15.
- 154They kept detailed records on this aspect of their work as well. See, e.g., Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, Report of School Buildings Owned by Bureau R., F. & A.L. and by Other Parties Engaged in the Education of Freedmen, in the State of Alabama Month of June 1870 (1870), microformed on Records of the Education Division, Roll 15.
- 155See African Americans and Education During Reconstruction: The Tolson’s Chapel Schools, Nat’l Park Serv., https://perma.cc/6BQ2-QLZY(last updated Oct. 6, 2020).
- 156See id.
- 157Ch. 200, 14 Stat. 173.
- 158Mark A. Graber, The Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill’s Constitution, 94 Tex. L. Rev. 1361, 1367 (2016).
- 159Andrew Johnson, Veto Message to the Senate (Feb. 19, 1866), in Veto Messages of the Presidents of the United States, with the Action of Congress Thereon 289, 292 (Washington, Government Printing Office 1886).
- 160Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866 § 13, 14 Stat. at 176.
- 161Freedmen’s Bureau Acts of 1865 and 1866, U.S. Senate, https://perma.cc/C8Q9-YDBT.
- 162See U.S. Const. art. V.
- 163Act of July 6, 1868, ch. 135, § 2, 15 Stat. 83, 83.
- 164Act of July 6, 1868 § 2, 15 Stat. at 83.
- 165Compare Act of July 6, 1868 § 2, 15 Stat. at 83, with Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866 § 5, 14 Stat. at 174, and Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1865 §§ 2, 4, 13, 13 Stat. at 508.
- 166Black, supra note 83, at 1063.
- 167See Landmark Legislation: The Fourteenth Amendment, supra note 115.
- 168Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA), U.S. Dep’t of the Interior, https://perma.cc/8HB3-FN8U.
- 169Id.
- 170David Wallace Adams, Education for Extinction: American Indians and the Boarding School Experience, 1875–1928, at 26–27 (1995).
- 171Raymond Cross, American Indian Education: The Terror of History and the Nation’s Debt to the Indian Peoples, 21 U. Ark. Little Rock L. Rev. 941, 952 (1999).
- 172Id. at 950.
- 173See David. H. DeJong, Promises of the Past: A History of Indian Education in the United States 34 (1993).
- 174Cross, supra note 171, at 950–52.
- 175Id. at 954.
- 176Robert B. Porter, The Demise of the Ongwehoweh and the Rise of the Native Americans: Redressing the Genocidal Act of Forcing American Citizenship upon Indigenous Peoples, 15 Harv. BlackLetter L.J. 107, 110–11 (1999).
- 177Id. at 129–30.
- 178For a discussion of this evolving “wardship” status, see generally Nancy Carol Carter, Race and Power Politics as Aspects of Federal Guardianship over American Indians: Land-Related Cases, 1887–1924, 4 Am. Indian L. Rev. 197 (1976).
- 179See, e.g., Porter, supra note 176, at 115–16.
- 180For a sample of this treatment, see generally David E. Wilkins, American Indian Politics and the American Political System (2007).
- 181Merrill E. Gates, Land and Law as Agents in Educating Indians, in H.R. Doc. No. 109, Seventeenth Annual Report of the Board of Indian Commissioners, The Year 1885 (1886), reprinted in Americanizing the American Indians: Writings by the “Friends of the Indian,” 1880–1900, at 46 (Francis Paul Prucha ed., 1973).
- 182Id. at 46, 52.
- 183See Porter, supra note 176, at 115–23.
- 184See id. at 133–34, 136.
- 185Pub. L. No. 68-175, 43 Stat. 253.
- 186Id. at 124.
- 187Thomas J. Morgan, Instructions to Indian Agents in Regard to Inculcation of Patriotism in Indian Schools, in H.R. Exec. Doc. No. 51-1, pt. 5, at clxvii (1890), reprinted in Americanizing the American Indians, supra note 181, at 257.
- 188W.T. Harris, The Relation of School Education to the Work of Civilizing Other Races (1895), reprinted in Proceedings of the Thirteenth Annual Meeting of the Lake Mohonk Conference of Friends of the Indian 33, 37 (Isabel C. Barrows ed., Boston, The Lake Mohonk Conference 1896).
- 189See Jon Reyhner, American Indian Boarding Schools: What Went Wrong? What Is Going Right?, 57 J. Am. Indian Educ. 58, 60 (2018).
- 190See Sarah Klotz, Impossible Rhetorics of Survivance at the Carlisle School, 1879–1883, 69 Coll. Composition & Commc’n, 208, 212 (2017) (placing “the boarding school project within a long history of literacy training as settler colonialism in North America” (emphasis in original)); see also Adams, supra note 170, at 137.
- 191See Adams, supra note 170, at 137–38.
- 192See Klotz, supra note 190, at 212–13.
- 193Id. at 213.
- 194Embe, Stiya, a Carlisle Indian Girl at Home (Cambridge, Riverside Press 1891).
- 195Amanda J. Zink, Carlisle’s Writing Circle: Boarding School Texts and the Decolonization of Domesticity, 27 Stud. in Am. Indian Literatures 37, 37 (2015).
- 196Id. at 37–38.
- 197Embe, supra note 194, at 108.
- 198Id.
- 199Id.
- 200See Adams, supra note 170, at 138–41.
- 201See Klotz, supra note 190, at 212–13.
- 202See Adams, supra note 170, at 25–27, 140–41, 291.
- 203Richard H. Pratt, The Advantages of Mingling Indians with Whites (1892), reprinted in Americanizing the American Indians, supra note 181, at 260–61; see also Adams, supra note 170, at 52.
- 204Adams, supra note 170, at 141 (quotation marks omitted).
- 205See generally Lori V. Quigley, Thomas Indian School Social Experiment Resulting in Traumatic Effects, 14 Jud. Notice 48 (2019).
- 206Freedmen’s Bureau, supra note 141.
- 207See Stanley, supra note 146, at 36.
- 208Id. at 36–37.
- 209See Raymund Munts & David C. Rice, Women Workers: Protection or Equality?, 24 Indus. & Labor Rels. Rev. 3, 3–5 (1970).
- 210State Minimum Wages, Nat’l Conf. of State Legislatures (Jan. 5, 2021), https://perma.cc/54VK-YYYN.
- 211Reyhner, supra note 189, at 74.
- 212See generally Ctr. on Educ. Pol’y, A Brief History of the Federal Role in Education: Why It Began & Why It’s Still Needed (1990).
- 213Black, supra note 83, at 1065–66.
- 214See Adams, supra note 170, at 26–27.
- 215See Gary B. I, 957 F.3d 650–52.
- 216See Glucksberg, 521 U.S. at 721.
- 217Id. (quotation marks omitted) (quoting Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325, 326 (1937)).
- 218There is considerable scholarship arguing that both requirements are indeed met. See generally Black, supra note 83; Friedman & Solow, supra note 33.
- 219See Black, supra note 83, 1089–90.
- 220See Adult Literacy in the United States, supra note 19.
- 221Aaron Tang, Ethan Hutt & Daniel Klasik, Opinion, A Constitutional Right to Literacy for Detroit’s Kids?, N.Y. Times (Apr. 26, 2020), https://perma.cc/E24E-5STP(arguing that systemic inequality in U.S. education cannot be properly addressed solely in federal courts).