Volume 90.4
June
2023

Print
Article
Volume 90.4
The Fourth Amendment Without Police
Shawn E. Fields
Assistant Professor of Law, Campbell University School of Law.

I am grateful for conversations and discussion at the 2021 Southeastern Association of Law Schools Conference, at which I received helpful input from Cynthia Alkon, Mitch Crusto, Raff Donelson, Jancy Hoeffel, Nicole Iannarone, Christopher Lund, Carla Reyes, Daniel Schaffa, Kate Sneddon, Neil Sobol, Scott Sundby, Anna VanCleave, and Howard Wasserman. I also received enormously helpful comments and feedback from Dwight Aarons, Kristen Bell, Zac Bolitho, Bobbi Jo Boyd, Marcus Gadson, Tony Ghiotto, Noël Harlow, Orin Kerr, Cortney Lollar, and Gustavo Ribeiro. All errors are my own.

What role will the Fourth Amendment play in a world without police? As academics, activists, and lawmakers explore alternatives to traditional law enforcement, it bears asking whether the amendment primarily tasked with regulating police investigations would also regulate postpolice public safety agencies. Surprisingly, the answer is often no. Courts are reluctant to recognize protections from government searches or seizures outside criminal investigations, and they are even more reluctant to require probable cause or a warrant for such conduct. Thus, by removing most public safety functions outside the criminal sphere, abolitionists also move intrusive government conduct outside these traditional strictures and guardrails. This Article provides the first sustained evaluation of the Fourth Amendment’s limited role in a postpolice world and examines the implications of this reality.

Print
Article
Volume 90.4
Regulatory Trading
David A. Weisbach
Walter J. Blum Professor of Law, University of Chicago Law School.

Send comments to d-weisbach@uchicago.edu. I am thankful for Jen Nou and Mark Templeton for discussions and the many valuable comments from workshops at the University of Chicago Law School and Washington University Law School. Special thanks to Richard Sandor for allowing me to participate in his class at the University of Chicago Law School, The Law and Economics of Natural Resource Markets.

Regulatory trading systems, such as the SO2 cap-and-trade system, are ubiquitous in environmental and natural resources law. In addition to cap-and-trade systems for pollutants such as SO2, NOx, and CO2, environmental and natural resources law uses trading in areas such as endangered species, water quality, wetlands, vehicle mileage, and forestry and farming practices. Trading, however, is rarely used as a regulatory approach in other areas of law. This Article seeks to identify the reasons for this dichotomy. To understand the dichotomy, the Article examines the uses of trading in environmental and natural resources law, where it has been successful, and where problems have arisen, including hot spots problems, environmental justice problems, measurement problems, and moral problems with the use of markets. It then considers the possibility of trading in six nonenvironmental areas of law to see whether trading can be helpful, and if not, why not.

Print
Comment
Volume 90.4
The Long Arm of Bostock v. Clayton County: Opening 42 U.S.C. § 1985(3) to Claims of Anti-LGBT Discrimination
Jason Hanselman
B.A. 2020, Marquette University; J.D. Candidate 2024, The University of Chicago Law School.

Many thanks to the staff and editors of the University of Chicago Law Review for their incisive feedback on previous drafts.

This Comment argues that Justice Gorsuch’s opinion is not merely relevant for the scope of Title VII but also has ramifications for the scope of § 1985(3) because it gives rise to three key propositions: (1) federal law now condemns anti-LGBT discrimination, affording special protections to LGBT folks; (2) discrimination against LGBT folks necessarily constitutes discrimination on the basis of sex; and (3) legislative history should only be used if the relevant statute is genuinely ambiguous. Justice Gorsuch has thus provided LGBT plaintiffs with a master key, suggesting arguments tailored to each circuit’s position on sex-based discrimination, such that any circuit should permit LGBT folks to use § 1985(3) in the wake of Bostock.

Print
Comment
Volume 90.4
Covenant Control: The Case for Treating Uptier Transactions as a Form of Corporate Control
Ryan Schloessmann
B.A. 2017, Carleton College; J.D. Candidate 2024, The University of Chicago Law School.

I would like to thank Professors Douglas Baird, Vincent Buccola, and Tony Casey, and the editors and staff of the University of Chicago Law Review for their thoughtful advice and insight.

In recent years, uptier transactions have emerged as a novel way for distressed companies to restructure their debt obligations, resulting in unforeseen and inequitable outcomes for investors in corporate debt. Uptier transactions depend on provisions in credit agreements that permit debtholders with a majority stake in a class of debt to make decisions on behalf of all debtholders. Distressed companies take advantage of these provisions by colluding with a majority of debtholders to shift economic value from the remaining debtholders to themselves. As this Comment demonstrates, these transactions are likely to be value destructive and present an issue for capital markets. Unfortunately, the contractual solutions available to debtholders to prevent uptier transactions either are insufficient or impose substantial costs on parties.

Print
Comment
Volume 90.4
A Gricean Theory of Expressive Conduct
Richard P. Stillman
B.A. 2011, Swarthmore College; Ph.D. 2021, The Graduate Center, City University of New York; J.D. Candidate 2024, The University of Chicago Law School.

I would like to thank Professor Geoffrey Stone for his guidance and supervision. Special thanks are also due to the editors and staff of the University of Chicago Law Review for improving this Comment through their incisive and thoughtful feedback.

This Comment addresses how courts should decide whether non-verbal conduct is “speech” within the meaning of the First Amendment. In Spence v. Washington, the Supreme Court devised a two-part test for determining whether non-verbal conduct is expressive, which has subsequently become known as the “Spence test.” In its subsequent cases, however, the Court has made clear that the category of “expressive conduct” includes a wider variety of non-verbal behaviors than a literal reading of the Spence test would suggest. Drawing on the work of twentieth-century philosopher Paul Grice, this Comment proposes a two-part test that captures the expressive character of this wider variety of behaviors, and demonstrates how lower courts might employ the test either as a replacement for, or as a supplement to, the Spence test.